About some Greek thinkers
By Daniel
Paquet dpaquet1871@gmail.com
ARISTOTLE
“Certain
notions of the separate, isolated existence of phenomena and their
interconnection appeared together with the emergence of philosophy. Thus, the first Greek philosophers took
interconnection as the basic principle for explaining various phenomena. By taking a substance or natural phenomenon (air,
water, fire ) as the original source, Greek philosophers showed that all phenomena
had appeared as a result of certain changes in that substance (phenomenon) and
that, being but different states of one and the same nature, they were
intrinsically interconnected, passing from one into another and into the
original source. (...)
The first
Greek philosophers regarded interconnection as the interpassage of phenomena
into each other. Later, however, this
view was succeeded by another one, according to which interconnection was a
mechanical joining and unjoining of the same immutable elements. This view was held by Empedocles and
Anaxagoras, among others. Aristotle overcame the limitations of
this dependence of things. Aristotle wrote: ‘All relatives have correlatives…’ He was the first to declare ‘relation’ as a
category, thus lending it the necessary generality.
In contrast
to Plato, Aristotle rejected the existence of an insurmountable wall between
possibility and reality, although he acknowledged the separate, independent
existence of these two categories. He
believed that the possible can turn into the real, and vice versa. He considered primordial matter to be pure
possibility, while the form that ultimately merged with God, who was the form
of forms, was in this view pure reality.
The blending of form with matter resulted in the appearance of
qualitatively definite things possessing possible and real existence and changing
when one opposite (possibility) changed into another (reality). According to Aristotle, the transition of possibility into reality did not occur
as a result of forces and tendencies inherent in a thing – it was connected
with the action of external factors, of outside force, i.e. of a certain really
existing thing. From a thing existing as
a possibility, he believed, as a result of the action of another thing, also
existing in reality.”[1]
Aristotle was born in 384 B.C. in the northern town of Stagira, far from the intellectual centre
of Greece. His father, Nicomachus, was a
physician attached to the court of Philip of Macedon, and a plausible
speculation ascribes to paternal influence not only Aristotle’s later
connection with the Macedonian dynasty but also his powerful interest in, and
love of, things scientific.
In 367, Aristotle moved south to Athens.
Whether or not he was originally attracted there by the pull of Plato, he quickly became associated
with the Academic circle, that
brilliant band of philosophers, scientists, mathematicians and politicians
which gathered in Athens under the inspiring leadership of Plato.
In 323 Alexander
died in Babylon. When the news reached
Athens Aristotle, unwilling to share
the fate of Socrates, left the city lest the Athenians put a second philosopher
to death. He went to Chalcis, where he
died a few months later. His will, which
has survived, is a happy and humane document.”[2]
Furthermore,
Aristotle says: “Whatever is incapable of participating in
the association which we call the state, a dumb animal for example and equally
whatever is perfectly self-sufficient and has not need to (e.g. a god), is not
a part of the state at all.
Among all men, then, there is a natural
impulse towards this kind of association; and the first man to construct a
state deserves credit for conferring very great benefits. For as man is the best of all animals when he
has reached his full development, so he is worst of all when divorced from law
and justice. Injustice armed is hardest
to deal with; and though man is born with weapons which he can use in the
service of practical wisdom and virtue, it is all too easy for him to use them for
the opposite purposes. Hence man without virtue is the most savage, the most
unrighteous, and the worst in regard to sexual license and gluttony. The virtue of justice is a feature of a
state; for justice is the arrangement of the political association and a sense
of justice decides what is just.”[3]
PLATO
“The
ancient Greek philosopher Plato…
represented objective idealism. In his
view, the real world around us consisted of ideal substances, while sensuous
things were but imperfect copies of the latter that emerged as a result of the
blending of an idea with amorphous matter existing merely as a possibility. (…)
Platonism
is based on the division of all that exists into the real world, consisting of
general ideas (‘ideal essences’), and the unreal world, made up of assorted sensuous
things, being just a reflection or a shadow of the real world (the world of
ideas). To illustrate the correlations
between the world of sensuous things (the unreal world) and the world of ideas
(the real world), Plato gives the
following example. Imagine a man chained to a pole in a dark cave, his back
always to the entrance from where the sunlight comes, so that he cannot see
what is going on outside the cave.
Plato believes that the world of ideas is integral
thanks to the Idea of the Good, and is eternal, whereas separate things and
phenomenon are transient and temporary.
They emerge from the amorphous and vague being (matter) as a result of
combining with a certain idea, but as soon as the idea abandons the thing it
has created, the latter ceases to exist.
It follows then that real things and phenomena are created by ideas,
which ultimately take their beginning in God.
Plato’s theory of ideas was severely criticized by Aristotle, whose teaching is the
pinnacle of ancient Greek philosophy. (…)
Aristotle proved that no general ideas exist outside and
independently of things. Aristotle vacillated between
materialism and idealism. He held that
all things originated from primordial matter characterized by vagueness and a
lack of form, i.e. in fact it was just the possibility of existence. This possibility turned into a real sensuous
thing only when matter combined with a form (Aristotle’s term), which gave it definiteness. Although Aristotle,
world view was basically materialist, it also had idealistic overtones.” [4]
Plato was born in 427 BC, (he died in -347) some four
years after the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War and just over a year after
the death of Pericles. His father,
Ariston, who died when Plato was a few years old, was a member of an old and
distinguished Athenian family, as was also his mother Perictone. Ariston and Perictone had two other sons,
both older than Plato, Adeimantus
and Glaucon, who are two of the main characters in the Republic. After Ariston’s death
Pericton married again, as was the normal Greek custom, her second husband
being Pyrilampes, a close friend and supporter of Pericles and himself
prominent in public life. Plato thus came of a distinguished family
with many political connections. Through
his stepfather he had a link with Pericles, who gave his name to the great age
of Athenian history, and to whom Athenian democracy, as Plato knew it, owed many of its characteristic features…
And it is
important to remember what a democracy in fifth- and fourth century Greece was
like. The Greeks lived in city-states,
small communities consisting of a ‘city’ nucleus, with an area of agricultural
land attached, from which the urban population varied in size, but were all
small by the standards of a modern city.
The population of Athens when Plato
was born was perhaps 200-300,000, including men, women, and slaves; and
Athens was by Greek standards large. In a democracy the vote was confined to
the adult male citizen population. At Athens slaves may have numbered some
60-80,000, and there were perhaps 35 – 40,000 ‘metics’, that is residents who
because they had been born elsewhere did not qualify for citizenship.”[5]
Greater
Athens’ population is 3,413,990 in 2015 accordingly to Le Petit Larousse dictionary
at page 1297.
“The
question of possibility and reality has been attracting philosophers’ attention
since ancient times. Plato’s solution, for instance, was to
distinguish possible form actual or real existence. He held that the world of ideas and ideal essences
possessed the property of real being, whereas the world of things possessed
possible being. Since it could not
change into reality and acquire real existence. There was, Plato believed, a necessary division between real and possible
being.”[6]
SOPHOCLES
We then had
a ‘dialogue’, with two giants of human thought; tragedians of this era were
also brilliant thinkers. “Sophocles (born ca. 496 B.C., died
after 413) was one of the three major authors of Greek tragedy. Of his 123 plays, only seven survive in full.
Antigone, written and first performed in
the late 440s B.C., is among his most often revived plays; its strong roles,
and its conflicts between individual morality (championed by a brave young
woman) and the overbearing political needs of the state, have never lost their
compelling interest through the generations.”[7]
Others
include: Ajax, The Women of Trachis,
Electra, Philoctetes.”[8]
Archives:
La Vie Réelle
[1] Sheptulin,
A. P., Marxist-Leninist Philosophy,
Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1978, pages 187-188, 239
[2] Aristotle, Introduction to Ethics, Penguin
Classics, Markham, 1976, pages 10-11
[3] Aristotle, The Politics, The State as an Association,
Penguin Classics, Toronto, 1981, page I ii
[4] Sheptulin, pages 18,
38-40
[5] Plato, The Republic, Translator’s Introduction,
Penguin Classics, Toronto, 1987, page xxv
[6] Sheptulin, pages
238-239
[7] Sophocles, Antigone, Dover Publications, Inc., New
York, 1993, page v
[8] Grene,
David; Lattimore, Richmond, The Complete
Greek Tragedies, A Washington Square Press Book, New York, 1973, 264 pages
Aucun commentaire:
Enregistrer un commentaire